Newsgroups: talk.politics.guns
From: [l v c] at [cbvox1.att.com]
Subject: The  ~Sporting Purpose~  Issue  in  Gun-Control  Policy
Date: Thu, 26 May 1994 15:52:37 GMT

The following article by Preston K. Covey appeared in Gun Week,
it is reprinted here with permission by him.

--
Larry Cipriani, [l v cipriani] at [att.com] or attmail!lcipriani

----------------------------------------------------------------------

The  ~Sporting Purpose~  Issue  in  Gun-Control  Policy

Preston K. Covey
Director,  Center for the Advancement of Applied Ethics
Carnegie Mellon University

Presented at the Second International Symposium on Leisure & Ethics
Denver, CO,   April 11, 1994


	In the context of gun-control policy, what does ~sporting purpose~
mean?  Unfortunately, the term is uniquitous but nowhere defined; its
meaning must be divined from the legislative and enforcement debates. 
While the history of this notion in 20th-century gun control is itself
very interesting, let~s just take the most recent example: on February
28, 1994, the ATF reclassified certain 12-gauge shotguns as ~destructive
devices~ on the basis of the following statutory provision (Section
5845(f)(2), Chapter 53, Title 26) of the United States Code:

~[D]estructive device~  means . . . any type of weapon . . . which will
. . . expel a projectile . . ., the barrel or barrels of which have a
bore of more than one-half inch in diameter, except a shotgun . . .
which the Secretary or his delegate finds is generally recognized as
particularly suitable for sporting purposes . . . .  

The archtypal ~destructive device~ this legislation meant originally to
control was on the order of a grenade launcher or artillery piece.  But
the barrel of a 12-gauge shotgun, at .60 caliber, happens to be over
half an inch in diameter.  Hence, the explicit exemption for shotguns. 
However, this exemption leaves a discretionary loophole: it is limited
to shotguns  which the Secretary or his delegate finds is generally
recognized as particularly suitable for sporting purposes.  This
provision evidently gives the Secretary of the Treasury (who oversees
the ATF) the authority to add certain ~non-sporting~ firearms to the bin
of banned weapons.  

	The express criterion  for exemption is ~sporting purpose.~  But what
precisely is the standard  for this privileged exemption?  While the
Secretary~s discretionary judgment may legally be sufficient, the
standard for guiding his appraisal of ~suitability for sporting
purposes~ is whether a gun is generally recognized  as such.  But by
what standard do we judge general  recognition?  This standard is
nowhere defined.  But the operative standard comes to this: the two most
popular sporting purposes, hunting and target shooting, are evidently
taken to satisfy the requirement. 

	Unfortunately, this statutory language governing ~destructive devices~
reflects the sum total specification of the ~sporting purpose~ standard
available in federal law, as an internal ATF memorandum on the recent
shotgun reclassification attests:

This ruling represents a small step in imposing rational controls over
the non-sporting assault-type weapons addressed in the Feinstein bill.
With the exception of these large bore shotguns, there is currently no
sporting purpose test in existing federal law governing the types of
firearms that can be manufactured and sold commercially.  [But]
Feinstein~s bill would ban . . . these shotguns as well as a host of
other rifles and handguns that also provide tremendous firepower, while
serving no legitimate sporting purpose.  (Tartaro, 1994, emphasis mine.)

In short, the ATF has the authority to ban only large bore shotguns; a
ban on rifles and handguns which serve ~no legitimate sporting purpose~
must be effected by new legislation, such as the Feinstein bill.  New
legislation must now either beg the question of what constitutes
~legitimate~ sporting purpose or else clearly define a standard (which,
of course, it does not do).  But we see here a clue to the ulterior
purpose of the de facto  ~sporting purpose~ standard:  to ban firearms
that ~provide tremendous firepower, while serving no legitimate sporting
purpose.~  The targeted firearms are advisedly combat weapons that are
currently legal to own.  One combat weapon ban, the Schumer bill (HR
3527), is entitled (in part) the ~Recreational Firearms Protection Act.~
 By what principle of ~legitimacy~ or ~recreational~ utility are
firearms nominated for such patronizing protection by our government? 
To paraphrase Uncle Remus, ~The tar baby, he don~t say nuthin.~   The
tacit hypothesis here is this: 

	If  combat  firearms  serve  no  ~legitimate~  sporting  purpose,  
	they  may  or  should  be  banned.  

	I pose two problems for the ~sporting purpose~ hypothesis:  (I) The
hypothesis presupposes without argument that it is a proper function of
government to prescribe ~legitimate~ leisure; such unprincipled and
therefore arbitrary authority is politically pernicious, a threat to all
socially harmless leisure, not to say morally controversial but harmless
leisure.  Hunting, as a so-called ~blood sport,~ is morally
controversial in many quarters of our society, but its tools as such are
implicitly protected under the prevailing ~sporting purpose~ standard.
With an essentially undefined and therefore arbitrary standard of
~legitimate sporting purpose,~ just how long will the equally deadly
tools of the recreational hunter or target shooter stay the ban?  Be
that as it may, (II) the assumption of this hypothesis is in any case
demonstrably false -- namely, the assumption that combat firearms serve
no ~legitimate~ sporting purpose. 

	Problem I

 	The ~sporting purpose~ hypothesis presupposes that government has the
authority to judge what counts as ~legitimate~ leisure or sport and the
power to curtail leisure activities which it deems illegitimate.  The
~Recreational Firearms Protection Act~ (reminiscent of the ~Firearms
Owners Protection Act~?) decidedly does not protect all forms of
firearms recreation, such as collecting and recreating with combat
firearms.

	This arrogation of authority is tantamount to legislating ethics in the
discretionary realm of leisure, where our modes of creating meaningful
lives are presumably innocent until proven guilty of actionable harm to
others or to society.  This arrogation of authority is pernicious
because it offers no principled rationale or limitations and thereby
threatens the freedom of moral choice at the heart of all  leisure
pursuits, not just those involving firearms.
. 
	We must distinguish here between two categorically different grounds
for coercive limitations on liberty -- either for outlawing an activity
itself (like gambling) or for outlawing the means for pursuing an
activity (like child pornography or hard drugs).  Two categorically
different grounds for limiting liberty are:  (1) moral disapproval  and 
(2) demonstrable social harm.  They are hardly on a par.  

	Of these, in our system of criminal justice, demonstrable social harm
is presumably a necessary condition for criminalization:  by this
standard, not even all uncontroversial  moral wrongs are proscribed by
criminal law:  for example, many forms of lying or promise-breaking are,
at best, grounds for civil tort action.  The burden of proof, then, is
either to demonstrate serious harm, irrespective of moral disapproval,
or else to produce a principled rationale for why certain activities
which are morally controversial but not in themselves harmful should be
criminalized.  Moral disapproval by itself  is no basis for
criminalization,  absent some further discriminatory principle that
answers the perennial questions for legislating morality: What or whose
standard of moral approbrium shall prevail and be enforced by law in
morally controversial cases?  And by what rationale or principle?   

	One principle for prohibiting activities that may be morally
controversial but that in themselves are not harmful turns on the
distinction between distributive and aggregative harms.  Distributively 
harmful activity is such that serious harm or social cost attaches to
each and every individual instance of the activity in itself.  An
example is murder, each act of which is harmful.  Aggregatively  harmful
activity is such that harm does not accrue to each and every individual
enjoyment of the activity in itself; rather, because some  people~s
activity is harmful, serious social harm results in the aggregate.  An
example is the use of motor vehicles, which some people drive
recklessly. 

	As a case in point, the civilian ownership of firearms is aggregatively
 rather than distributively  harmful: merely owning a firearm produces
no harm in itself; but a small minority who abuse firearms generate
serious aggregative harm:  the annual size of the offending minority
happens to be small indeed -- for example, less than 1/100th of one
percent of the law-abiding gun-owning public turns homicidal 1 --
although the harm they do is grievous.  A prominent social philosopher
puts the consequent political dilemma in perspective:

If the state prohibits [responsible and law-abiding] persons from
possessing handguns [say, or firearms ~not  generally recognized as
particularly suitable to sporting purposes~], it must tell them, in
effect, that they cannot do something which is harmless, because others 
cannot be trusted to do the same thing without causing grievous harm.  
(Feinberg, 1984, p. 194). 

	On this view, the justification for gun bans (which disenfranchise a
vast majority in order to try to affect a miniscule minority) must show
at least two things:  that the harms outweigh the benefits and that the
prohibition in question will in fact redress the balance of harm over
benefit.  Both are problematic, particularly the latter: showing that
disarming the law-abiding majority will in any wise affect the criminal
minority (Polsby, 1993). But this is one proper function of government,
balancing individual and social benefits and harms for the protection of
the commonweal.  If it is also a proper function of government to judge
the ~legitimacy~ of leisure on moralistic grounds, absent a showing of
harm, the standard of ~legitmacy~ must be specified; in the case of
~legitimate~ sporting purpose, the standard remains unspecified and,
thus, unprincipled and arbitrary.

	The invocation of ~sporting purpose~ is also problematic because it
presupposses without argument that ~sporting purpose~ should carry
special privileged weight in the balancing of harms and benefits.  I
argue, on the contrary, that the weightiest interest in the balance
scale of benefits is not the recreational value of firearms, but rather
their value for the protection of innocent life against criminal threat. 

	The protective value  of firearms is distributive and has two
dimensions:  One is their defensive utility, the metric for which is the
actuarial rate at which armed civilians successfully defend against
criminal threats -- most recently estimated at two million cases a year
(Kleck, 1993).  The other is the incommensurable residual value of this
option in self-defense itself, regardless of the actuarial utility of
having a gun or ever having to use it.  This residual value includes our
claim-right to be allowed effective means  of self-defense (namely,
firearms), which is directly derivative from our paramount right to
self-preservation.  

	Actuarially, a firearm happens to be one~s best option in the gravest
extreme 2 when, by the universal standard of justifiable homicide, an
innocent person is in imminent and otherwise unavoidable danger of death
or grave bodily harm.   Removing this option imposes a severe limitation
on the exercise of our uncontroversial right to self-defense. 

	Also included in the residual value of firearms for protection is our
putative obligation  to defend innocent life in the gravest extreme:
many hold that this is not only a right but a moral and civic duty.  In
his article ~A Nation of Cowards~ (1993),   Jeffrey Snyder put the
matter forcefully:

Although difficult for modern man to fathom, it was once widely believed
that life was a gift from God, that not to defend that life when offered
violence was to hold God~s gift in contempt, to be a coward and to
breach one~s duty to one~s community.

	In addition to the distributive  protective value of firearms, there
are two aggregative benefits of armed citizens, a social value and a
political value.  Their social value consists in their role in the
reduction of criminal violence or social disorder by either deterrence
or interdiction.  Their political value  consists in their role as a
defense or deterrent against government violation of the social compact.
 These functions may be arguable, but they must be fairly accounted and
weighed in the balance scales on their merits, not summarily ignored.

	Now, the protective, social and political values of civilian firearms
are all predicated on their utility for combat.  Pace the more radical
pacifists, combat is not inherently bad:  combat can be defensive as
well as aggressive and combat is justifiable, and arguably obligatory,
in defense of innocent life.  There is a utopian conceipt that civil
society must eschew the justifiable use of deadly force (or deadly
weapons) in the hopes of thereby banishing violence; but a utopian
mandate to eschew the moral right,  nevermind the moral obligation, to
defend innocent life belies the very value of human life itself.  In his
classic essay ~Utopia and Violence,~  Karl Popper put the matter
plainly:  

. . . we must not allow the distinction between attack and defence to
become blurred.  We must insist upon this distinction, and support and
develop social institutions . . . whose function it is to discriminate
between aggression and resistance to aggression.  (Popper, 1965)

As for delegating the obligation for the defense of innocent life to
others, such as the police,  Jeffrey Snyder poses another moral
challenge:  

How can you rightfully ask another human being to risk his life to
protect yours, when you will assume no responsibility yourself?  
(Snyder, 1993)
. . . while we wait for laws to restrain men, we will be condemned to
wonder why criminals have no respect for our lives, when we ourselves do
not value our lives enough to assume the responsibility to defend them 
(Snyder, 1994).

These are serious moral issues to weigh in the balance scales before
dismissing combat firearms for serving ~no legitmate sporting purpose.~
Indeed, morally compelling (nevermind ~legitimate~) interests in
defensive combat place top priority on precisely those firearms that are
~generally recognized as particularly suitable~ for combat -- not merely
sporting -- purposes. Invocation of ~sporting purpose~ as a basis for
special treatment belies this priotiy.

	The prevailing notion of ~sporting purpose~ in the gun-control debate
is problematic in three respects: (1) because it assumes without
argument that the government of a pluralistic society may legislate
~legitimate~ leisure absent demonstrable social harm, (2) because the
privileging of ~sporting purpose~ firearms ignores the preeminent
protective, social and political values of combat firearms and (3)
because it is gratuitous if not disingenuous for the following reason: 
if ~sporting purpose~ or recreational value were the only interest in
the balance scale to counterweigh the aggregative harms of
civilian-owned firearms, gun bans would hardly be as controversial as
they are today.  Suppose, unrealistically (Polsby, 1994), that all
combat firearms were effectively removed from both civilian and
criminals hands.  Hunting and sanitized target firearms would then
become the tools of choice of criminal violence:  How long would their
~sporting purpose~ stay their banishment?  The inexorable logic of
selective gun bans is that they must evolve into total bans: in the end,
~sporting purpose~ would be revealed to be the gratuitous and
question-begging ploy it has been from the beginning.  

	Problem II	 

	Consider again the tacit hypothesis behind the prevailing notion of
~sporting purpose~: If combat firearms serve no ~legitimate~ sporting
purpose,  they may or should be banned.  I argue by counter-example that
the assumption of this hypothesis (that combat firearms serve no
legitimate sporting purpose) is false. While I make a case for
~legitimate~ sporting uses of combat firearms,   I do not hereby beg any
questions about gun control.  My argument here is simply that ~sporting
purpose~ is quite beside the point in gun-control policy if only because
combat firearms do in fact enjoy ~legitimate~ sporting uses.

	The assumption that firearms can be neatly and categorically segregated
by purpose and, hence, that firearms ~generally recognized as
particularly suitable~ for combat  can serve no legitimate sporting 
purpose is based on a no-brainer fallacy: 

Some guns are useful only for assault,  warfare,  murder  or mayhem --
like the so-called ~assault weapons~  (which are properly called
~combat~ firearms).  

Law-abiding civilians have no legitimate interest in assault, warfare, 
murder, or mayhem.

Therefore,  law-abiding civilians have no legitimate interest in combat
firearms.

	The first premise and conclusion above are flatly false.  Law-abiding
civilians have a legitimate interest in combat for their own
self-defense.  Therefore, law-abiding civilians have a legitimate
interest in combat firearms -- and, most certainly, in training
therewith.  This legitimate interest in firearms training for defensive
purposes naturally gives rise to both legitimate and even socially
useful sporting purposes for combat weapons,  which I will call ~combat
weaponcraft,~ my own sport of choice.

	Firstly:   combat weaponcraft is a sport in any common sense of the
term ~sport~ in which fishing, hunting, or target shooting are sports.

	In fact, target shooting is itself but a variant of combat weaponcraft.
Indeed, historically, in America and Europe, today~s sanitized forms of
target shooting -- as ~pure~ sport -- are abstracted from the discipline
of combat weaponcraft.  Historically, in origin, target shooting was a
practical sport with a clear social mission, promoting marksmanship and
combat training;  it served to ensure that the civilian population was
~well regulated~ in combat weaponcraft to perform their civic duties in
maintaining the social order and serving the common defense.  According
to one leading historian of small arms:

The concept of target shooting as a pure sport does not begin to emerge
until after the First World War; indeed, Britain held aloof from the
early development of international shooting competition because it was
considered too abstracted from the military function of marksmanship.

It was the goal of universal civilian training in marksmanship which
also inspired the subsequent smallbore shooting movement.  The .22
rifle, portrayed recently in the press as the archtypal ~purely
sporting~ firearm, was seen in urban Edwardian Britain as the prime tool
of military training.  At the same time, NRA service rifle marksmanship
was directed by Lord Roberts towards the modern concept of ~combat
shooting~:  rapid and snap shooting on moving and disappearing targets. 
(Munday, 1988)

	Harking to these historical roots, and by contrast with more ~pure~
forms of target shooting, the regimens of combat weaponcraft include a
vast variety of stress-inducing tactical drills and dynamic scenarios
that test one~s tactial judgment and moral decisionmaking as well as
safety and marksmanship under duress.  Competition is both against the
clock and rigorous standards of qualification as well as against other
competitors.  

	While there are hundreds of local, regional, national and international
competitions, one can compete solo against the rigorous performance
standards calibrated for survival ~in the gravest extreme.~  These
rigors include the observance of ethical and legal standards for the
judicious use of deadly force.  Also of the highest priority are
firearms safety standards, which are religiously observed: the same
rules of safety apply on the firing range and in a threat situation;
there is no ~double standard~ for safety.  Consequently, the
practitioners of this sport are amongst the most reliable and
conscientious in safety discipline.  

  The denial of so-called sporting  purpose (or recreational uses) for
firearms advisedly designed for combat purposes is simply dogmatic,
based on an ignorantly narrow definition of the shooting sports  as
being limited to either hunting or so-called target shooting.   There
are harmless, responsible and socially useful sporting  uses (a myriad
of organized civilian competitions) for every manner of firearm,
including military small arms, combat weaponry and even machineguns.
This is a matter of sociological fact, not political doctrine.  There
are organized competitions after the manner of the highly stylized
International Practical Shooting Confederation (IPSC), the Camp Perry
matches which prominently feature military longarms, various national
and regional civilian machinegun matches, the Steel Challenge and
Bianchi Cup matches, the Second Chance and Three Gun combat shooting
competitions, and the annual National Tactical Invitational organized by
the civilian American Tactical Shooting Association, which represents
the state-of-the-art in tactical firearms training scenarios for
civilians and law enforcement. 	Amongst the many and varied competitions
in combat weaponcraft, the epitome of this practical sport is the
National Tactical Invitational Match. The NTI is attended by both law
enforcement professionals and civilians, including leading police
firearms instructors who are themselves private citizens, but it is
organized by private citizens -- an example of private enterprise with a
socially responsible mission par excellence.

	Secondly:  The sport of combat weaponcraft is eminently and morally
legitimate on the following forthright grounds: those of us who engage
in it do so safely and responsibly; we hold society and innocent others
harmless thereby and continually improve ourselves in skill, judgment
and responsibility.  If there are other criteria of ~legitimacy,~ I
should like to know what they are.  Certainly, general popularity,
absent actionable harm, is no more a requirement of legitimate sport or
recreation than it is of religion or speech. The safety record of
practitioners of any of the variety of combat weaponcraft itself is
impeccable.

	Thirdly:  in addition, combat weaponcraft is a sport with a social
mission and social utility: it serves as a technology-transfer mechanism
by advancing the state-of-the-art of threat-management and defensive
firearms training for both law enforcement and civilians.  Civilian
re-enactment societies and groups employing licensed Class 3 weapons
(including fully automatic firearms and machineguns) serve as mock
adversaries in training exercises for units of our armed forces.

	Like most innovations in firearms training outside the military, the
combat shooting arts have been pioneered by private citizens.  Unlike
the Olympic sporting events that were abstracted from age-old military
experience (the marathon, biathlon, javelin, etc.), the practical
shooting sports are devised to refine and inform modern technique ~where
the rubber meets the road~ -- with state-of-the-art combat weapons.  Its
techniques and technology are evolved through open competition, then
applied, tested and refined through professional training and practical
experience.  The symbiotic feed loop is like that among research
universities, industry, and government.  

	Many of the best ideas in combat training and technology evolve from
the innovations of civilian practitioners.  In my own case, one-handed
mastery of combat weaponry proves informative to officer-survival
training:  necessity is the proverbial mother of invention, and my
contributions to police survival training increase my satisfaction in my
sport of choice.  So I turn my recreation to a practical social purpose,
by training police officers in combat weaponcraft as well as in the law
and ethics of deadly force that properly delimit its use.  Most of my
colleagues do likewise, by sharing their knowledge and skills with
others, either law enforcement or fellow citizens or both, thereby
helping to ensure a safer and more responsible shooting public.

	Finally,  I must speak to the morally controversial nature of my sport,
 since some consider gun ownership itself, nevermind combat weaponcraft,
 ~demented and bloodthirsty~  (see the discussion of moralistic
objections to civilian gun ownership in Kates, 1991).  
	
	To quote Gerald Fain from his essay, ~Moral Leisure~ (1991), ~Leisure .
. . is  the  opportunity  to  choose  how  one  ~ought  live.~~ 
Spending one~s discretionary time in the refinement of any of the combat
or martial arts is such a choice.   Combat weaponcraft is morally
controversial in the important sense in which all  moral choices are
open to question and demand an accounting when moral sensibilities
collide.  I can only sketch the moral dimensions of my sport here; this
stands as an account, not a proper defense against those who are
radically and ignorantly at odds with the gun culture or who regard it
as ~simply beastly~  (as quoted in Kates, 1991).  There, perhaps, n~er
the twain shall meet.

. . . now a virtuous life requires exertion, and does not consist of
amusement.  (Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1103)

	The sport of combat weaponcraft is neither a leisurely recreation nor a
mere amusement, but rather an avocation dedicated to the disciplined
development of both moral virtues and practical skills in the service of
an avowed moral obligation and social mission. While we may defend
innocent life on the basis of the most fundamental of moral and legal
rights,  practitioners of combat weaponcraft also avow a moral and civic
obligation  as well -- an obligation, at the least, to our loved ones,
an obligation to prevent our spouses from being widowed or our children
orphaned -- or worse.  Some take it further, as a civic or more
altruistic obligation to defend any threatened innocent life.  This is
not a vigilante ethic;  it is neither more nor less than the lawful
defense of innocent life allows.  (For a proper definition of
vigilantism, see Kates, 1991).

	Contrary to stereotype, practitioners of my sport are not training to
shoot their way to glory in the Armed Citizen column of  American
Rifleman  magazine.  None but psychopaths and felons who understand the
realities of lethal encounters romanticize the necessity of self-defense
as an opportunity for glory. Law-abiding practitioners of combat
weaponcraft live in no such fool~s paradise.  The ethos that informs our
sport is no less demanding than that of any serious martial art, wherein
power and responsibility are commensurate:  it requires soul-searching
reflection on fearsome realities and on the rigorous requirements for
transmuting the awesome responsibility for the judicious use of deadly
force into decisive fortitude, a disciplined mindset, morally discerning
judgment, well deliberated action, and the tactical skill to both ~do
the right thing~ and survive in the ~moment of truth,~  in the gravest
extreme.   Karl Popper~s point bears repeating:

. . . we must not allow the distinction between attack and defence to
become blurred.  We must insist upon this distinction, and support and
develop social institutions . . . whose function it is to discriminate
between aggression and resistance to aggression.  (Popper, 1965)

The lawful avocation of combat weaponcraft is, above all, a social
institution that respects this distinction and defends this cornerstone
of civil society.

Notes

1.  The 1991 Chicago Police Department in-depth study of 20,264
homicides from 1965-91 found that 75% of criminal homicides are
committed by recidivists with prior records of criminal violence. On
this sample, assume that recidivists with prior records commit 75% of
our homicides; then, 25% of our annual gun homicides are committed by
previously law-abiding gun owners, such that less than 1/100th of 1% of
the law-abiding gun-owning public turn homicidal each year:  18,000 gun
homicides x .25 = 4500 / 60 million lawful gun owners = .000075 = .0075%
= less than 75/10,000ths of 1% = .75/100ths = less than 1/100ths of 1%.
This estimation is comparable to another measure of the miniscule number
of irresponsible armed citizens: since the new concealed carry law in
Florida was enacted in 1987,  less than 1/100th of 1% of the issued
licenses have been revoked for the commission of any crime involving a
firearm (Snyder, 1993, p.49).  Another telling indicator of the
relatively low incidence of harm done by armed citizens is the
following:  only 2% of civilian shootings involve an innocent person
mistakenly identified as a criminal, compared with an error rate of 11%
for the police, while at the same time armed citizens justifiably kill
three times the number of felons a year as do police  (Snyder, 1993, p.
50).  

2.   According to Kleck (1991), resistors fare better than non-resitors
and gun-defenders fare best of all.  As stated by one prominent critic
of defensive firearms ownership, Arthur Kellerman:  ~If you~ve got to
resist, your chances of being hurt are less the more lethal your weapon.
 If that were my wife, would I want her to have a thirty-eight special
in her hand?  Yeah.~   (Japegna, 1994)


References

Gerald S. Fain, ~Moral Leisure,~ in Gerald S. Fain (Editor) Leisure and
Ethics: Reflections on the Philosophy of Leisure  (Reston VA: American
Alliance for Health, 1991).

Joel  Feinberg, Harm to Others, Volume I of The Moral Limits of the
Criminal Law  (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984).

Ann Japenga, ~Would I Be Safer with a Gun?~  Health   March/April 1994.

Don B. Kates, ~The Value of Civilian Handgun Ownership as a Deterrent to
Crime or a Defense Against Crime~  American Journal of Criminal Law 
Winter 1991.

Gary Kleck, National Self-Defense Survey conducted February-April 1993
(yet unpublished).

Karl Popper, ~Utopia and Violence,~ in Conjectures and Refutations: The
Growth of Scientific Knowledge  (New York: Harper & Row, 1965).

Richard A.I. Munday, ~Civilian Possession of Military Firearms,~ UK
Handgunner  January/February 1988.

Jeffrey S. Snyder, ~A Nation of Cowards,~ The Public Interest  Fall
1993;  ~A License to Save Your Life?~  The Washington Times  January 20,
1994.

Joseph P. Tartaro, ~Hindsight: Background on the Shotgun
Reclassification,~ Gun Week  March 18, 1994.